A while ago, at http://childmyths.blogspot.com/2013/05/when-children-lie-evade-misrepresentor.html,
I pointed out that it takes a good deal of cognitive ability for a child to
tell a convincing lie. Lying is a skill that develops through a combination of
maturation and learning. It is a real part of typical development and does not
indicate that the child is emotionally disturbed. Naturally, parents would like
their children not to evade or attempt to deceive them-- but equally naturally, they would like the
children to tell appropriate social lies (“Oh, Grandma, I love these purple
socks with sky-blue pink polka dots--
nobody else has anything like them!”). Lying has a conventional aspect as well as a cognitive one.
When we think about lying, it’s all too easy to
confuse the cognitive skills involved in an effective lie with the moral development that forbids lies
under some (but certainly not all) circumstances. When people lie, they may or
not be breaking moral codes. Understanding when lying is immoral and when it is
not is a complicated matter and takes experience and maturation to master. If I
go to a dinner party and tell the hostess I like the salad when I actually find
it disgusting, few would say that lie was an immoral one; they would be more
likely to say that it was at least rude, perhaps even unnecessarily cruel (and
therefore perhaps immoral), if I confessed what I really thought. On the other
hand, if a friend of mine is arrested for theft, and I state that she was with
me at the time even though she wasn’t, my lie, although kind to my friend,
would be both illegal and immoral because it could lead to the conviction of an
innocent person and other bad outcomes. (This
all just goes to show that the idea of “learning right from wrong” is an enormous
over-simplification.)
So, lying, or choosing not to lie , is partly a
matter of cognitive skills that help a child decide what’s likely to be
believed and what will happen if he or she is or is not believed. But
development of those skills happens in parallel with the learning of
conventions about lying and truth-telling and with the development of moral decision-making.
In an article in Child
Development Perspectives, Kang Lee of the University of Toronto recently
discussed the developmental trajectory of lying in typically-developing
children (Little liars: Development of verbal deception in children. 2013, Vol.
7, pp. 85-90). Among other things, Lee
looked at existing evidence about children’s lies in two situations-- when they were caught after having done
something wrong, and when they needed to
back up a lie they had already told. Only about 30% of 2-year-olds lied to
cover their transgression, but by age 6 more than 80% of children did so. When they had lied (in an experimental
situation, where they had been told not to peek at a hidden toy), 2- and
3-year-olds often denied that they had peeked, but then blurted out “Barney!”
(correctly) when asked what they thought the toy was. Older children got
gradually better at covering up, but were initially clumsy; Lee reported that
one 5-year-old said she didn’t look, but felt the toy, and it “felt purple” so
she knew it was Barney.
Lee also described the nonverbal behavior of lying
children, and noted that when they lie deliberately, they often mimic “truth-telling”
behavior, by making direct eye contact in some situations, and by averting
their eyes (as if trying to remember) in others. These are behaviors that are likely to be
much influenced by culture and convention, and Lee’s discussion emphasized the
role of cultural expectations in determining how children use “white” or “social”
lies. Preschoolers disapprove somewhat of social lies, but when they reach
adolescence, after years of instruction and modeling by adults, they see such
lies as a positive contribution to social interactions.
It’s obvious that most children lie and that skill
in lying is evidence of continuing cognitive development. Paradoxically, although
we say that lying is wrong and don’t like to have children do it, we may also need
to think of some aspects of lying as positive signs of moral development and
empathy. When lying is excessive or appears unnecessary or even foolish to
adults, we need to examine the social context, the child’s understanding and
intentions, and the child’s expectations based on family and cultural rules. There’s
no need to jump to the conclusion that childhood lying is a symptom of mental
illness or of character flaws greater than those most human beings display.
An interesting question that has not received much
exploration is this: at what age do children know that we are lying to them? Does
the subject make a difference? When they
discover that the story about Santa wasn’t true, and that the sick kitten did
not go to live with its grandma, do they also come to suspect that other things
we say are less than truthful? As is so often the case, it’s what we do rather
than what we say that sets the standard.
No comments:
Post a Comment