Some weeks ago, when I had written a post about the
Oregon psychologist Kali Miller and the revocation of her license (http://childmyths.blogspot.com/2015/03/psychology-license-revoked-become.html),
one Robert Plamondon commented with severe criticism of psychology licensing
boards and advice that unhappy clients of psychologists should sue the
practitioners directly instead of going through the licensing board. I pointed
out in response that when children were the patients, they did not have the
capacity to sue for personal injury, and if their parents had made the decision
to seek the treatment, or even carried out some of the treatment themselves,
the parents would probably not bring suit on the children’s behalf (behalves?).
I see now that Plamondon has a web site, www.unlicensed-practitioner.com,
which purports to provide resources to help alternative and unlicensed
practitioners operate “legally and ethically” in Oregon. As far as I can tell,
Plamondon objects to decisions made by the Oregon board of psychologist
examiners, but in addition he favors mental health treatment by unlicensed
persons in a general sort of way. This may be in part because he himself is practicing
as a hypnotherapist.
I would be the first to admit that national professional
organizations like the American Psychological Association and the National
Association of Social Workers have strong “guild” mentalities and are much concerned
about their professional hegemony. The current scandal about the involvement of
APA with approval of torture is evidence that focusing on putting the
profession forward can interfere with everyday ethical decisions, not to speak
of professional ethics. But to my mind these are not reasons to abandon
regulation through licensure and other methods.
Why do I think this? What are the advantages to the
public of licensing mental health professionals? Why, especially, do the
educational requirements for licensure benefit the public? There are two
primary reasons for requiring practitioners to meet licensing standards and to do so through formal education-- and neither of them has much to do with
whether the practitioner has learned specific techniques of therapy.
The first concern has to do with education about the
nature of evidence and the ways we can test the effectiveness of treatments.
Plamondon himself states that the major difference between psychologists and
counselors is that psychologists are trained to do scientific research. From the
point of view of patients, there is probably no advantage to visiting a practitioner
who is doing actual research (i.e.,
collecting data systematically), but there is an enormous advantage to going to
someone who can read research, which
few people are able to do well unless they have studied research methods. Practicing
psychologists, social workers, and other mental health professionals should be
capable of understanding when research evidence supports the use of a treatment
method, when there is no such support, and when a treatment is potentially
harmful to patients. No licensure can insure
that practitioners do their homework, but licensing standards can require that professionals have gone through
the formal educational process that should provide them with the skills to
understand research evidence.
Unlicensed practitioners may be competent and
careful about the evidence basis of the treatments they use, but it appears likely
that most of them are not. This point is made by Plamondon’s tendency to refer
to “unlicensed and alternative” practitioners. Alternative practitioners by
definition use methods that lack evidence of effectiveness; if this were not
the case, there would be nothing “alternative” about them. Plamondon himself
displays his lack of concern with evidence of treatment effectiveness by his
references to such methods as Neurolinguistic Programming (NLP) and
sensorimotor psychotherapy. These therapies, which Plamondon apparently finds admirable,
are without acceptable research support. It is not illegal to use them, but it
would be difficult to argue that such use is demonstrably in the best interest
of the public. In some cases, methods used by alternative practitioners are not
only ineffective, but potentially harmful—as in the case of “conversion”
therapy and the related “holding” therapy.
These facts lead us to a second issue about
education required by licensing standards. Licensed mental health practitioners
have to show that they have been through educational programs that included
study of professional ethics. Unlicensed practitioners may be perfectly ethical
people in their daily lives, but may be without training in some of the special
issues of professional ethics. For example, in daily life, it is “not nice” but
not strictly unethical to tell a juicy piece of gossip that has been disclosed
to us; in mental health practice, confidentiality is an ethical obligation that may be handled well only if someone has
been trained to think clearly about conflicting motives and benefits. (Does the
psychologist tell a patient’s family member that the patient seems to be
considering suicide? ) Similarly, in daily life, it does no harm for someone to
socialize with a person he employs or works for; in mental health work, the
wearing of “two hats” in dual relationships creates a variety of ethical
problems, which may be avoided only when earlier training and practice have
alerted a practitioner. No one would claim that all licensed mental health
professionals are always able to make the right choices in professional ethics
(as any state’s list of disciplinary decisions shows), but a requirement of appropriate
education excludes from practice persons who have never received formal
instruction about ethical choices.
In his earlier comment, Plamondon suggested that
patients who have been injured should bring personal suits against mental
health practitioners rather than bringing a complaint to a licensing board. Let
me point out that personal injury suits are time-limited and in some states
cannot be brought more than a year after the event that caused the claimed
injury. Although it can happen that the time limit clock starts when the person
realizes that an injury was done, in that case the defense for a practitioner may be a motion to dismiss the
case because the individual “should have known” earlier that there had been an
injury caused by a treatment. A number of suits by adults who were harmed by
inappropriate mental health practices when they were children have failed
because the individuals did not manage to understand that they had been harmed
and to find counsel for several years after the 18th birthday. Thus
personal injury suits are often ineffective ways to obtain redress for people
who have been harmed by alternative mental health practices. Similarly, suits
for fraudulent deception are likely to fail either on the ground that an injury
or loss cannot be clearly demonstrated, or on the ground that the practitioner believed
the treatment would be effective and not harmful. Protection of commercial
speech in the United States makes fraud even more difficult to prove.
Because of the difficulties of finding justice for people
who have been harmed by alternative or unlicensed mental health practitioners,
I would argue that in spite of many and various holes in the system, the best
choice for the patient is a licensed mental health practitioner, and the best
governmental choice is to continue and
strengthen licensing requirements.